|
the politics of preemption
GENOCIDE, SELF-DEFENSE AND INTERNATIONAL LAW
by
LOUIS RENÉ BERES
___________________________
Louis
René Beres is Professor of Political Science at Purdue
University. He is author of many books and articles dealing
with international politics. His columns have appeared in the
New York Times, Washington Post, The Jerusalem
Post and OUPblog
(Oxford University Press). This article was originally publised
in Israel
Journal of Foreign Affairs.
Under
authoritative international law, aggressive war and genocide
need not be mutually exclusive. On the contrary, war can intentionally
create the conditions that would make genocide possible; it
can also be the more direct or immediate instrument of closely
related crimes against humanity. It follows then, as Iran comes
ever closer to achieving a viable nuclear weapons capability,
that Israel has an especially good reason to fear future conflicts
with such an aggression prone Islamic republic.
Ultimately,
any war launched by Iran could become genocidal.
Language
has meaning. On July 23, 2014, Iran’s Supreme Leader,
Ali Khamenei, called openly for the annihilation of Israel.
For some time before that day, Iranian presidents, whether Hassan
Rouhani or Mahmoud Ahmadinejad, had been proclaiming their desire
to bring about Israel’s “disappearance.”
What
still needs to be examined, more seriously and systematically,
is whether these Iranian leaders have been calling for literal
genocide, and whether, in response, Israel still maintains any
legal authority to strike first.
Israel
already has codified and customary rights to request a punitive
General Assembly resolution, even one calling for Iran’s
expulsion from the United Nations. While such a diplomatic rejoinder
to Iran’s presumptively genocidal pleas could be entirely
permissible and compliant with the law, it would also have little
determinable effect upon Iran’s planned or considered
military intentions. Of course, any such request could also
be rejected by UN member states.
Under
international law, genocide has a very precise jurisprudential
meaning. This identifiable content is most conspicuously and
authoritatively defined in the “Convention on the Prevention
and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide.” According to
that 1948 treaty, which entered into force in 1951 and is also
binding upon non-signatory states as customary international
law, pertinent violations are not confined to any specifically
enumerated acts committed with “intent to destroy . .
. ” They also include “conspiracy to commit genocide”
and “incitement to commit genocide.”
No
state can ever be obliged to passively await an expected genocide.
This principle, “peremptory” because it is fundamental
and overriding (a jus cogens norm, identified at the 1969 Vienna
Convention on the Law of Treaties), includes those more or less
exterminatory belligerencies that masquerade as war.
Under
both codified and customary legal rules, every state maintains
an “inherent right” to individual or collective
self-defense.
As
express violations of the 1948 Genocide Convention, and its
derivative norms, Iranian calls for Israel’s “disappearance”
are not simply calls for cartographic exterminations. Under
law, they are also, quite literally, genocidal provocations.
In view of its corollary unwillingness to abide by obligations
under both the UN Charter and the 1968 Nuclear Nonproliferation
Treaty (NPT), Iran has chosen to disregard the binding norms
of general international human rights law. Moreover, these complementary
jus cogens violations are enlarged by Iran’s support of
Hizbullah, and by its support for certain other kindred terrorist
groups (both Shi’a and Sunni).
In
the chaotic Middle East, the geostrategic axes of conflict are
complex and sometimes overlap. This bewildering situation could
sometime require Israel to choose between having to combat one
genocidal terror group (e.g., Shi’a Hizbullah), or another
(e.g., Sunni ISIS).
Undeterred
by a patently impotent diplomacy of “sanctions,”
including even the P5+1 agreement of July 14, 2015, Iran is
finalizing its preparations for nuclear weapons capability.
The Tehran regime may still regard nuclear weapons as a potentially
acceptable means with which to create “a world without
Zionism.” As for any sort of reconciliation with Israel,
Iran’s former president has already spoken quite frankly:
“Anybody who recognizes Israel will burn in the fire of
the Islamic nation’s fury; any Islamic leader who recognizes
the Zionist regime means [sic] he is acknowledging the surrender
and defeat of the Islamic world.”
Like
it or not, Israel may still face a zero-sum “game”
with Iran, a life-or-death contest in which one state’s
ultimate victory will plausibly require the other’s total
defeat. Very soon, therefore, Israel’s leaders might have
to make certain unprecedented existential decisions, inter alia,
on launching defensive first strikes.
Operational
and jurisprudential judgments on this urgent issue are discrete,
and thus need to be appraised separately. Here, we are interested
only in the second standard of assessment. In short, we must
inquire: Could such strikes be legal? An informed answer requires
both knowledge and nuance. Would the case for the legality of
Israeli preemptive action be strengthened by Iran’s willingness
to go beyond aggression (another expressly codified crime under
international law) to genocide? And does the Genocide Convention
address the vital security issue of anticipatory self-defense?
For
Israel, size counts. At less than half the area of a typical
county in California, Israel’s “wiggle room”
in matters of strategic survival is woefully limited.
Ironically,
over several years, although Israel has never actually threatened
Rouhani or Ahmadinejhad with preemption, Tehran has somehow
managed to extrapolate just such a threat from an introspective
awareness of its own first strike intentions. Quite strategically,
perhaps, knowing that Israel has the most to fear from Tehran’s
unhindered nuclear program, Iranian leaders habitually complain
that it is the “Zionists” who are preparing for
aggression.
From
time to time, Iran hints obliquely at its presumed right to
attack Israel first, in permissible self-defense. In this regard,
Iran has essentially been threatening to preempt an Israeli
preemption. Although unlikely, Israel could still decide to
fulfill Iran’s own contrived warnings. Any such authentically
lawful preemption, assuredly non-nuclear, will have been mandated
by the Tehran-induced strategic spiral of “escalation
dominance.”
In
this context, history may be relevant. Facing formidable Arab
attacks in June 1967, the Jewish State opted to strike first.
From the standpoint of international law, this preemption against
enemy military targets was a classic example of anticipatory
self-defense.
On
June 7, 1981, Israel launched Operation Opera against Saddam
Hussein’s then-developing nuclear reactor outside Baghdad.
Officially, this preemptive attack on Osiraq—an attack
that ultimately saved a great many American and other lives
ten years later, during the first Gulf War, or Desert Storm—was
also an expression of anticipatory self-defense. Interestingly,
however, because Iraq had always considered itself to be formally
“at war” with Israel, the Jewish State could just
as easily and correctly have regarded this essential act of
protection as something else. More precisely, back in 1981,
taking an alternative legal position, Prime Minister Menachem
Begin could also have justified Operation Opera as a permissible
action, one taken tactically in the wider context of already
ongoing belligerency.
It
is notable also that legally, Begin chose to link Operation
Opera to the prevention of “another Holocaust.”
The core rationale of including anticipatory self-defense under
customary international law has been the prevention of aggression,
not the prevention of genocide. Logically, it was not until
1951, when the Genocide Convention first entered into force,
that the legal question of defensive first strikes to forestall
such enumerated crimes against humanity could even have been
raised.
After
the Holocaust, and the subsequent Nuremberg Trials, it became
clear that the traditional prerogatives of sovereignty in world
law could no longer remain absolute, and that the once-legitimate
cover of “domestic jurisdiction” would now have
to exclude certain egregious violations of human rights. With
this fundamental transformation, individual human life was to
be held sacred everywhere, and individual states were no longer
automatically precluded from entering into the “territorial
sphere of validity” of other states. On the contrary,
from then on, the traditional norm of “non-intervention”
would sometimes have to yield to compelling obligations of “international
concern.”
In
principle, at least, it became a reasonable expectation that
all states, either individually or collectively, would acknowledge
a distinct and overriding legal obligation to prevent Nuremberg-category
crimes (after 1951, crimes of genocide) being committed in other
states, even to the point of sometimes undertaking appropriate
interventions within those sovereign states. This critical obligation
was strongly reinforced at Articles 55 and 56 of the United
Nations Charter, a key international law document, which has
the formal status of a multilateral treaty. Today, we speak
of all such permissible interventions as “humanitarian.”
Alternatively, diplomats and scholars may prefer the closely
related term, the “Responsibility to Protect,” or
“R2P.”
Whichever
term is preferred, the international legal order now expects
all states to demonstrate responsibility toward one another
(in effect, to be their “brothers’ keepers”),
and take necessary action to prevent genocide and certain corollary
crimes against humanity. Examples of this collaborative expectation,
a concept that makes unassailably good sense in our anarchic
system of world law—a fractionated balance-of-power system
that first came into being in 1648, when the Treaty of Westphalia
ended the Thirty Years’ War, and one that has yet to be
replaced with genuinely effective supra-national legal institutions—can
be found in at least four prominent post-Holocaust cases:
--
the Tanzania-led invasion of Uganda in 1979, which put an end
to Idi Amin’s almost decade-long genocide against the
Acholi and Langi tribes;
-- the Vietnamese invasion of Cambodia in 1979, which put an
end to the Khmer Rouge mass murder of almost 2,000,000 people,
a genocide that targeted several diverse populations along many
different ethnic, cultural, and tribal lines;
-- the 1971 genocide against Bengali people, the “Bangladesh
Genocide,” which covered an area originally known as “East
Pakistan,” and that was finally stopped by massive Indian
military intervention; and
-- the 1994 invasion of Rwanda by Tutsi rebels who had been
“hosted” in neighboring Burundi, and also in the
Democratic Republic of the Congo. This genocide, perpetrated
largely by Hutu extremists (the Interahamwe), led to nearly
1,000,000 Tutsi deaths in ninety-days, making it the “swiftest”
genocidal mass murder in human history. It is also infamous
because the European powers, the United States, and the UN abandoned
every shred of compelling legal responsibility for humanitarian
intervention, or the responsibility to protect.
In
the Rwanda case, perhaps more conspicuously than anywhere else
in the past half-century, crude geopolitics easily trumped both
human rights and corresponding international law.
There
are other glaring examples of post-Holocaust genocides, all
of which further underscore how little progress has actually
been made in compliance with world law. These examples include
the Indonesian Genocide (1965–66) and the Darfur Genocide,
which began in 2003. Additionally, there are more recent examples
of humanitarian intervention in domestic war zones, such as
the multilateral Libya operation several years back to shield
Muammar Qadhafi’s domestic noncombatant targets from indiscriminate
attacks.
Still,
there have been no recognized examples of anticipatory self-defense
as a specifically preventative anti-genocide measure under international
law. The antigenocide interventions in the above cases were
directed toward the protection of imperiled human populations
in other states. They were not the preemptive expressions of
any imperiled state seeking to protect itself, “in whole
or in part,” from an anticipated genocide.
The
relentless fighting in Iraq and Afghanistan provides an example
of American preemption strategy for national self-defense against
terrorism, but not against any expected genocide. From the standpoint
of permissibility under international law, even this restricted
example of preemption is exceedingly problematic. Today, the
pertinent history of fabrication and contrivance in this particular
theatre of conflict is widely known.
Early
on, the George W. Bush administration went on record in favor
of a substantially broadened concept of anticipatory self-defense.
This very sweeping American doctrine asserted that traditional
notions of deterrence could not be expected to work against
a new kind of enemy. “We must,” according to The
National Security Strategy for the United States of America
(as published on September 20, 2002), “adapt the concept
of imminent threat to the capabilities and objectives of today’s
adversaries.” In this connection, it should be recalled
that the 1837 incident from which the modern legal concept of
anticipatory self-defense is drawn (the Caroline), related to
a threat that is “imminent in point of time.”
In
actual practice, this “adaptation” meant nothing
less than striking first against presumptively dangerous adversaries,
whenever deemed necessary. In any plausible comparison to Israel’s
current dangers from Tehran, however, the alleged risks to the
US from Saddam Hussein’s Baghdad reactor in the wake of
9/11 must appear vague and uncertain. In other words, when it
is finally understood, in terms of Israel’s present concerns
about an overtly genocidal Iran, any Israeli strategy of anticipatory
self-defense should be substantially less subject to any proper
jurisprudential doubt than was America’s Operation Iraqi
Freedom.
In
the post-Holocaust and post-Nuremberg international system,
the right of individual states to defend themselves against
genocide is reasonably overriding, and also beyond legal question.
This right does not stem directly from the language of the Genocide
Convention, which does not explicitly link genocide to aggressive
war, but it can still be extrapolated from the precise legal
language of anticipatory self-defense, including the 1837 case
of the Caroline and all subsequent authoritative reaffirmations
of law identifiable at Article 38 of the Statute of the International
Court of Justice. The right of anticipatory self-defense to
prevent genocide can also be deduced from certain basic principles
of self-protection codified at the 1969 Vienna Convention on
the Law of Treaties, and, more generally, from the confluence
of persistently anarchic international relations with now-obligatory
legal norms of basic human rights.
Should
Israeli decision makers ultimately determine that they do have
a compelling right to act first against Iran to prevent genocidal
aggression, any resultant preemptive Israeli action would still
have to be consistent with the laws of war in international
law, or the law of armed conflict. In detail, this means that
Israel would have to respect the always indisputable primary
belligerent requirements of “distinction” (avoiding
injury to noncombatants); “proportionality;” and
“military necessity.”
What
about the future? What happens next concerning a steadily nuclearizing
Iran? What about invoking anticipatory self-defense in this
particular case?
International
custom is one of several proper sources of international law
listed at Article 38 of the Statute of the International Court
of Justice. During the unsuccessful rebellion of 1837 in Upper
Canada against British rule, the Caroline incident established
that even a serious threat of armed attack may justify militarily
defensive action.
In
an exchange of diplomatic notes between the governments of the
US and Great Britain, then-US Secretary of State Daniel Webster
outlined a framework for self-defense that did not require a
prior attack. Here, a military response to a threat was judged
permissible, but only so long as the danger posed was “instant,
overwhelming, leaving no choice of means and no moment of deliberation.”
Strategic circumstances and the consequences of strategic surprise
have changed a great deal since the Caroline, thereby greatly
and sensibly expanding legal grounds for anticipatory self-defense.
Today, in an age of chemical/biological/nuclear weaponry, the
reaction time available to any vulnerable state under attack
could be a matter of mere minutes. From the special standpoint
of Israel, perhaps about to face a literally annihilatory Iran
armed with nuclear weapons, an appropriately hard-target resort
to anticipatory self-defense could be both lawful and law-enforcing.
Of
course, whether any such eleventh-hour preemption would also
make operational or tactical sense is another question entirely.
Before
the start of the atomic age, any justification of anticipatory
self-defense would have to have been limited to expected threats
of aggression from other states, not threats of genocide. Today,
however, the conceivable fusion of nuclear weapons capacity
with aggression could, ipso facto, transform certain wars into
an opportunity to commit genocide. Although there are no true
precedents of resorting to preemption as a law-enforcing means
of preventing genocide or “conspiracy to commit genocide”
by one state against another, the pertinent right to such pre-attack
self-defense is firmly rooted, inter alia, in the case of the
Caroline.
If
it was already legal, long before nuclear weapons, to strike
preemptively to prevent conventional aggression, how much more
permissible must it be to strike preemptively to defend against
a potentially genocidal nuclear war?
Some
legal scholars argue that the lawful right of anticipatory self-defense
first expressed in the Caroline incident has now been overridden
by the more limiting language of the UN Charter. In this view,
Article 51 of the Charter offers a much more measurably restrictive
statement on self-defense, one that relies on the strict and
tangible qualification of prior “armed attack.”
Nonetheless, this narrowly technical interpretation ignores
a much larger antecedent point, that is, that international
law is never a suicide pact.
Sensibly,
no law can ever compel a state to wait until it has absorbed
a devastating or even genocidal first strike before acting to
protect itself. Both the Security Council and the General Assembly
correctly refused to condemn Israel for its 1967 preemptive
attacks. Incorrectly, however, whether or not it had then accepted
the existence of a formal state of war between Israel and Iraq—a
condition of belligerency that was openly insisted upon by Baghdad—the
UN did condemn Israel for Operation Opera in 1981. This decidedly
wrongful condemnation was the direct result of regionally recurrent
geopolitical circumstances, familiar conditions wherein exterminatory
power politics easily trumped pertinent law.
Present-day
Israel is engaged in a state of protracted belligerency with
Iran. Again and again, Tehran has implied that a “state
of war” exists with Israel.
If
faced with an Iran in control of a nuclear arsenal, Jerusalem’s
only remaining strategic options would center upon some still-practicable
combination of active ballistic missile defense and nuclear
deterrence. In the best case, the resulting condition of mutual
nuclear vulnerability could resemble the earlier Cold War dynamics
of “two scorpions in a bottle,” the famous metaphoric
description first created by physicist J. Robert Oppenheimer.
In the worst case, however, it could become an institutionalized
“fusion” of mutual uncertainty and radical instability,
a potentially explosive posture more unpredictable than earlier
US–Soviet conditions of Mutual Assured Destruction (MAD).
In part, this would be because of the heightened probability
of Iranian leadership irrationality, a fearful prospect that
could very quickly immobilize operational nuclear deterrence.
Under
all relevant criteria of international law, Iran’s ongoing
stance toward Israel remains unequivocally genocidal. Because
international law is not a suicide pact, Jerusalem, now facing
a fusion of enemy nuclear capacity with enemy criminal intent,
reserves every reciprocal right of national self-protection.
In principle, at least, this includes even the undeniable right
to anticipatory self-defense.
Still,
Israeli calculations of genocide prevention will have to display
recognizably pragmatic as well as legal components. To be sure,
any rational Israeli decision to preempt genocidal actions by
Iran would have to be based not only upon due conformance with
the rules of applicable law, but also on absolutely overriding
strategic and tactical expectations. Understandably, therefore,
even if Israel were to accept the lawfulness of anticipatory
self-defense against Iran, it would act accordingly only if
such a complex defense plan could also be expected to work.
In
the end, Israel, already facing a nearly-nuclear Iran that could
potentially transform war into genocide, will likely forego
any eleventh-hour preemptions, and rely instead upon some expectedly
optimal combination of active defense and long-term nuclear
deterrence. With such a more-or-less prudential reliance, Jerusalem
would pay appropriate heed to Sun-Tzu. In The Art of War, the
ancient Chinese military strategist reminds us still that “subjugating
the enemy’s army without fighting is the true pinnacle
of excellence.”
|
wh |
|
|