aaron james's
ASSHOLES: A THEORY
reviewed by
ZACK DORFMAN
___________________________________________
Zack
Dorfman is associate editor at Ethics
& International Affairs where this review originally
appeared.
You
know him, I promise. He is difficult to avoid -- especially,
it seems, in our great urban centers. Curiously, the tonier
the Zip code, the more he seems to multiply like some droning,
infuriating ungulate. He is the person who weaves through three
lanes of traffic suddenly, without signaling. He is the person
who sits near you at a movie theater and proceeds to take a
phone call in the middle of the feature. He is the person who
cuts in front of you at your local lunch spot and pretends not
to realize that he is doing so, blithely. He makes his presence
felt: he is to be accorded special privileges, and his precedence
over you is to be accepted a priori. He is morally
stainless, for is it not merely in accordance with the natural
order of things for him to leave work early, but make you stay
late? For him to purchase a third term as mayor of The Greatest
City in the World™, no matter the laws or the express
desires of his own constituents? For him, as head of a major
investment bank, to cause through his avarice a global financial
crisis, but to blame that crisis on the fecklessness and greed
of middle-class homeowners? Or for him, as vice president, to
lie repeatedly to his compatriots, justifying an invasion of
a certain Middle Eastern country on the grounds that the dictator
he is seeking to depose is lying? Of course this is natural,
he thinks: of course. How could it be otherwise? This man, I
think you will agree, is an irritant. This man is an outrage.
This
man is an asshole.
He
is also, as Aaron James rightly observes in his convincing and
often quite funny book, Assholes: A Theory, an important
object of moral inquiry. Assholes are a social type. They arouse
our anger and indignation, and sometimes leave us with a vague
feeling of powerlessness and self-loathing. The strength and
nature of our reaction to assholish behaviour signals the extent
of the moral violation caused by it. Thus, for James:
The
problem of the asshole, then, is a problem for us all.
This
may sound overstated or glib, but James, a professor of philosophy
at UC Irvine, makes a rigorous case for why we should take the
problem of the asshole seriously. The book surveys diverse asshole
subtypes: asshole bosses, royal assholes, the corporate asshole,
and delusional assholes, to name just a few. But first James
neatly unpacks the basic features of this most loathsome individual.
For him, an asshole is defined by three important qualities,
which also serve to differentiate his behaviour from other morally
repugnant characters such as the jerk, or much more seriously,
the sociopath. First, the asshole considers himself -- and James
and I agree, assholes are almost always men -- to possess special
privileges or advantages over others. Moreover, he behaves in
a manner that reflects this belief (making the asshole distinct
from the mere egoist, who may believe that he is better than
others, but for a variety of reasons, does not act on this belief
systematically). Second, the grounds for this belief are assumed
and not argued for. An asshole believes deeply that he alone
deserves special treatment, that he is somehow entitled to it.
This kind of asshole behaviour, as James goes on to show, produces
both minor-league assholes, such as the line-cutter or reckless
freeway driver, as well as their major-league brethren, such
as, say, Donald Trump or Anthony Weiner. (Of course, significant
overlap is possible, and minor leaguers rarely disappoint when
called up to the big leagues). Third, and finally, assholes
are ‘immunized’ to the protests of others. An asshole
might hear you out, recognizing your complaints as valid in
an abstract way, but he never truly listens. A real asshole
does not feel the need to justify his behaviour to you, okay?
Thanks.
The
idea that the asshole is able to comprehend moral claims in
general, and the particular moral claims of other people, is
an important one. Crucially, it is how James is able to differentiate
the asshole from, for instance, the sociopath, who is unable
to reason in such terms. The sociopath does not understand rationally
why morality proscribes some actions and prescribes others,
or why morality finds certain kinds of behaviour praiseworthy
and other kinds censurable. According to his own demented understanding,
the sociopath does not break moral rules as much as operate
on an altogether parallel ethical plane. This is obviously monstrous,
and explains the overrepresentation of sociopaths in history’s
gallery of mass murderers: Pol Pot, Stalin, Mao and Hitler were
all pretty clearly sociopaths, and are also all quite clearly
among the worst people who have ever existed.
Comparatively
speaking, then, assholes are an altogether different breed,
and are generally far less destructive to the social order.
For assholes, while they might consider themselves special,
understand the strictures of morality, and often employ moral
reasoning to explain their own mistreatment. And, to risk stating
the obvious, your run-of-the-mill asshole would never condone
(even if he committed it) serious moral violations, such as
rape or murder. Assholish behaviour is therefore almost always
a venial (forgivable) sin, and not a cardinal one. Our reactions
to assholes differ accordingly: while sociopaths induce our
horror, given their manifest inhumanity, assholes tend to irritate
and anger us in more pedestrian ways. But while we feel ourselves
to be at a cognitive remove from true sociopaths, assholes --
since, as James argues, they are essentially rational beings,
capable of moral reasoning and affected by it -- are part of
our general social order. They are our moral intimates, and
so their casual disregard for our status as equals, worthy of
the same treatment and respect they would accord themselves,
makes the wound more visceral, if ultimately less destructive.
Sociopaths cause singular flesh wounds to our psyches; assholes,
a million little paper cuts.
The
reasons for this have to do with our conceptions of who we are,
and how we assign ourselves worth as human beings. As moral
creatures capable of rational action, we all feel that we are
entitled to respect, to the acknowledgment of our common humanity,
to what James calls the recognition that should be accorded
an autonomous thinking being whose existence is defined by the
same basic parameters as every other person. In failing to recognize
us as equal in this deeper moral sense, in arbitrarily placing
themselves above everyone else, assholes dehumanize us. In a
word, assholes violate our fundamental sense of human dignity.
The
concept of dignity, as Michael Rosen shows in the erudite and
compact Dignity: Its History and Meaning, possesses
a rarified pedigree. It has come to dominate the modern human
rights discourse, and has been a key concept in moral philosophy
since at least the 18th century. Yet, as Rosen rightly notes,
much confusion still exists about the meaning of the term, as
well as its sources. Is dignity merely expressive? That is,
is it a mark of certain outward forms of behaviour? Does it
inhere in institutions, such as when we refer to the dignity
of a certain public office? Does it apply only to human beings,
or could other living things be endowed with certain forms of
dignity? We are left in a conceptual morass. Perhaps, then,
Rosen suggests, we should take the opposite tack, and argue
with scholars such as Steven Pinker-- Rosen’s colleague
at Harvard -- that since the idea of dignity is simply reducible
to that of autonomy, we should do away with the first concept
altogether.
But
I am not so sure this is wise, and neither is Rosen. While the
meaning of dignity may vary, our conviction that the idea of
dignity captures something fundamental to our experience, something
that cannot be captured by the idea of autonomy alone, remains
constant. Dignity is an attempt to flesh out these
strands of thinking, and to investigate the commonalities, or
common sources, that link these different conceptions. To use
Hannah Arendt’s phrase, Rosen asks us to “think
what we are doing” when we confer dignity to a person,
or an office, or -- in a particularly memorable section -- to
a corpse. Although the book draws on sources as varied as Friedrich
Schiller, Cicero and Catholic social theory, Rosen leans most
heavily on Immanuel Kant (Critique of Practical Reason),
who is by far the most influential thinker to have written on
the subject. (In so many ways, when we speak about morality,
we inhabit Kant’s conceptual universe). He develops an
unusual account of Kantian morality that focuses on Kant’s
ideas about the “transcendental kernel” of the human
person, which is derived from our ability to be moral. For Kant,
morality is what makes us human -- and what confers dignity
upon us. In Rosen’s reading, then, while we certainly
possess stringent duties toward others, our primary moral duty
is to ourselves, because we are obligated to respect first and
foremost the foundation of our own humanity. For Rosen, too,
it is these moral duties that are the fundamental source of
our dignity, for they “are so deep a part of us that we
could not be the people that we are without having them.”
But if morality makes us human, then the opposite is also true:
immorality literally de-humanizes us. This is a harsh but precious
insight.
It
is also cold comfort to the asshole, who is most naturally at
home in a world of hyper-individualistic morality, one where
obligations toward others are argued to be minimal, or at least
apply only to the other, littler people, and never to the asshole
himself. Looked at from the perspective of American society
in general, this pretty accurately describes our Ayn Rand fever
dream: the idea that greed is good -- even morally laudable
-- and that the strong have every right, in fact, a duty to
rule over the weak. (For those enraptured by this idea, an investigation
into the origins of inequality is pointless: the weak are weak
because they are weak; the strong rule by virtue of their --
often material -- inheritances, which magically pass virtue
down from generation to generation, in the form of lucre).
This
strain of thinking offers a kind of social Darwinism on methamphetamines,
a philosophical gloss for the overstimulated and intellectually
bereft iPad generation. And, as James argues, it is in no way
far-fetched to connect the rise of assholish forms of behaviour
with social and institutional structures that may encourage
it. As he notes in his wonderful chapter on “asshole capitalism”
(which he considers a degraded form of capitalism, and not necessarily
a feature of the system itself), if those who succeed in today’s
economy tend to evince such characteristics, is copycat behaviour
not altogether likely, even rational? We have a long history
in this country of turning a blind eye toward the illegitimate
and immoral acquisition of wealth -- it only took the Kennedys
one generation to go from crooks to kings -- but it might be
worth considering whether the moral decay of 21st-century America
is related to this loss of dignity in the way we conduct our
business, and in the rotting away of the economic institutions
and values that reflected the dream of equality and fraternity,
and not just (negative) liberty. We have lost a sense of what
we owe each other: what constitutes our duties, and how these
duties should be negotiated as individuals and as a social collectivity.
All that remains inviolate is the norm of noninterference, or
the right to be left alone, to do what one wishes without considering
the wider effects of one’s actions. This is a desiccated
and corrupted understanding of liberty, and it would have been
unfathomable to our republican forebears in Greece and Rome.
If
asshole institutions or systems compromise our dignity, given
that they disregard our human -- moral -- core, so too do asshole
individuals. Assholish behaviour is a gesture of profound disrespect,
and the right to be respected and treated in a dignified manner
flows from the unique part of every individual that, perhaps
paradoxically, is the common inheritance of our species. Still,
as Rosen points out, the primary victim of such behaviour is
the moral offender himself, as his actions amount to a denial
of his own basic dignity. The asshole may not realize it, but
he is the saddest bastard of them all.