DOES MANLY COURAGE EXIST?
by
JOHN M. KANG
______________________________
John
M. Kang is a professor of law at St. Thomas University
in Miami Gardens, Florida. The unedited version of this essay
appears in the Nevada Law Journal.
If
you are a man, you probably have been subjected to it throughout
your life, I would imagine. I am referring to the societal summons
for you to fulfill the obligations of your gender: “step
up like a man,” “act like a man,” and a precursor
when you were very young, “big boys don’t cry.”
Me, I am especially taken with the injunction these days to
Man Up. More economical than its predecessors, the call to “man
up” pithily encapsulates the idea of manliness. For, to
be a man requires that you do something. Perhaps your dear mother
adores you as the apple of her eye, but, trust me, no one else
-- including (or is it especially?) your wife -- takes her cue
from Billy Joel’s schmaltzy serenade and loves you just
the way you are. (And who are you kidding? Not even your mom
really feels that way).
No.
You, my poor bloke, are instead told to comply with the expectations
of your community -- Man Up. What does manning up entail, though?
While its meaning, like that of many aphorisms, is imprecise,
the injunction to man up when distilled to its essence is meant
to prompt a man to comport himself with valour. For you are
only urged as a matter of idiom to man up in situations of danger.
Consider these examples: The rookie cop is solemnly tutored
by the hardboiled veteran detectives that he must man up sooner
or later and chase down suspects into dark alleys; the aging
quarterback is reminded by his fans to man up and wait in the
pocket for that ideal pass even as burly linemen charge to trounce
on him; the nebbish assistant professor is urged by his exasperated
wife to man up to his dean and ask why he was not promoted;
the habitual drunk is chided by his brother to man up and face
the fact that he is an alcoholic, and thus, to confront a humiliating
truth. As these examples suggest, men become men as a cultural
matter, only when they overcome some danger or risk, only when
they have demonstrated courage.
The
unstated but intimidating premise in these examples is that
failure to man up will emasculate you as a coward. To conscript
another epigram, albeit one more vulgar, you have to prove your
balls; should you falter, you would become the symbolic instantiation
for the corresponding female pudenda. (Tellingly, there is no
analogous admonishment for females to “woman up,”
although there are familiar warnings for women to tamp down
their masculinity, to cool their metaphoric balls, and to behave
demurely, more lady-like). This is not, furthermore, an exclusively
American phenomenon, as you probably surmised. The axiom that
men must prove their courage has been embraced by cultures around
the world, from nomadic Sub-Saharan tribes to sedentary suburbanites
in places like Bowling Green, Kentucky.
One can also consult older, more scholarly ruminations about
the connection between manliness and courage. The etymological
relationship between the two is instructive. Take the Latin
root vir. It forms part of ‘virtue’ which,
as conscripted by Christianity, has come to represent traits
modeled after Jesus, including humility and forgiveness. But
vir has a meaning which predates Christianity. For
the ancients vir was shorthand for ‘man.’ Those
words which derived from vir also referred to courage,
including virtus, or in its Anglicized form, ‘virtue.’
Consider how the mischievous philosopher Niccolò Machiavelli,
who, although living in a sixteenth-century Italy ruled in part
by the Pope, subverted the Christian ideal of virtue. Exhorting
his Italian prince to oust the invading Turks from Florence,
Machiavelli quoted Petrarch, the great Italian poet, who wrote:
No
olive branch of Christian forgiveness, Petrarch’s virtue
is itching for a fight – and a fierce one, at that, which
will “make the battle short.” Today, we find remnants
of this older Roman association between vir and manliness
in 'virility' and 'virulent,' with their respective connotations
of masculine spiritedness and potent destructiveness. Latin,
incidentally, was not alone in making the equation between being
a man and being brave. In ancient Greek, andr- meant
adult man and formed andreia, which meant courage.
In Hebrew GEV(B)URA (courage) was derived from the root G-B(V)-R
(man).
This
is interesting stuff, I hear you murmur, but, well . . . since
this essay appears in a law journal . . . what does it have
to do with . . . the law? A lot, actually. I have explored that
connection, between law and manliness, in previous work. And,
as much as I would enjoy surreptitiously rehashing it (although,
I confess, there is a bit of rehashing in this essay) and receiving
credit anew, I instead will invite the reader to peruse it elsewhere.
Perhaps I may suffice to say that the expectation for men to
behave with courage, or to suffer the ignominy of gender failure,
permeates the government’s justifications for a host of
policies. Congress defends restricting the military draft to
men based on the view that they are more courageous than women,
a decision upheld by the Supreme Court. Military courts have
only disciplined male soldiers for the formal offense of ‘cowardice,’
as though it were natural to expect courage from men, but not
women. State criminal laws exploit men’s fears by permitting
the excuse of deadly self-defense only for, in the law’s
words, a “man of courage,” not a “coward.”
A prestigious public military academy denied admission to women
because they were deemed to be lacking the courage which men
allegedly possessed. Judicial opinions, even landmark ones,
are not exempt; in cases whose facts would not seem to bear
any manifest relationship to gender, judges seek purchase for
their decisions by invoking the mantra that men must be brave.
In
treating courage as the chief virtue of manliness, we often
as not obscure manliness’s meaning.
THE
FIRST PARADOX: THE BURDENS OF MANLINESS
If
men are expected to prove their manliness through acts of valor,
there is no more vaunted arena than military combat.
Hockey,
boxing, football -- they are all dangerous -- but military combat
exposes you to something qualitatively different than the danger
of sport. War exposes you to unparalleled terror, to situations
that call for unimaginable reserves of courage. Unlike football,
military combat anticipates that you, a combat soldier, may
suffer a violent death, or -- perhaps just as wretched -- grisly
wounds that leave you pleading for your death. There is also
the corollary dread of having to bludgeon some anonymous chap,
like yourself, who has a family and who never did you any personal
harm.
Nevertheless,
many men enlist for service, or when drafted, resist temptations
to flee. A chief reason is that they are afraid of being outed
as cowards, as gender failures. Let Tim O’Brien, the novelist
and the combat veteran, narrate. O’Brien, a brainy and
sensitive college graduate, had been accepted for doctoral studies
in English literature at Harvard. Unfortunately for him, he
was also drafted by the military to fight in Vietnam. He did
not want to go -- and, although moral objections to the war
did stir him, O’Brien’s chief objection was fear
-- he was terrified of dying in combat.
But,
as much as he was afraid of violent death, he was even more
afraid of being denounced a coward -- and hence being publicly
unmanned -- by his tightly-knit Minnesota town.
So
O’Brien reported for duty. Once in Vietnam, O’Brien
realized that his fear of emasculation was shared by others.
For
O’Brien’s battalion, “the object was not valor,”
but instead, “they were too frightened to be cowards.”
THE
SECOND PARADOX: WHEN THE BURDENS ARE BLISSFUL
I have
suggested that what motivates male soldiers to do seemingly
brave acts is, ironically, a relentless fear that they would
be accused of being cowards. Thus, what passes for courage may
very well be a sort of cowardice in drag. But the anxiety of
a combat soldier is one that is mixed incestuously with a partial
love of the anxiety itself. What I have dubbed the burdens of
manliness exist as more than a collection of repugnant obstacles
whose negotiation yields nothing other than grimacing pain.
These burdens also paradoxically are experienced by men, or
at least some of them, as moments of matchless pleasure and
gratification.
Let
us turn to some firsthand narratives starting with that of Oliver
Wendell Holmes. Before he became the famous justice, a college-aged
Holmes enlisted as a young soldier in a Massachusetts regiment
during the Civil War. A member of a distinguished family in
Boston, he could have easily dodged military service, but he
was eager to prove his manliness. Holmes, indeed, proved it,
over and over, having been wounded thrice, one time nearly dying.
Looking
back, a middle-aged Holmes, now a judge on the Massachusetts
Supreme Court, reflected on his wartime experiences. He delivered
a Memorial Day speech at Harvard before the graduating class
of 1895. Holmes did not sugarcoat the horrors of war. He asked
the audience to imagine being a combat soldier, feeling “the
burst of the spherical case-shot,” seeing “the shrieking
fragments go tearing through your company,” and knowing
“the next shot carries your fate.” Imagine, too,
Holmes said, fighting for twenty-four hours and witnessing in
the morning “the dead and dying lay piled in a row six
deep,” as “your foot slip[s] upon a dead man’s
body.”
Why
do men like Holmes submit themselves to such ordeals? Holmes,
at one point, appears to attribute his willingness to what I
earlier called the burdens of manliness -- the collective expectation
that men fulfill their ideal as courageous beings or face unmanning
ridicule. “Who is there who would not like to be thought
a gentleman?” Holmes asked. “Yet,” he continued,
“what has that name been built on but the soldier’s
choice of honor rather than life?” “To be a soldier,”
Holmes said, “is to be ready to give one’s life
rather than to suffer disgrace.”
For
Holmes, however, there was more to being a man than having to
shoulder the fearsome burdens of manliness. Being a man entailed
the thrill of performing those ostensive burdens. “War,
when you are at it,” Holmes observed, “is horrible
and dull.” “It is only when time has passed,”
he explained, “that you see that its message was divine.”
For Holmes, war was divine in hindsight because it gave men
an opportunity to raise themselves from the idiotic and easy
pleasures of civilian life and to test their manliness to the
fullest in the forum of mortal struggle. Men in civilian life,
in “this snug, over-safe corner of the world,” spend
their lives, Holmes bewailed, “revolting at discipline,
loving flesh-pots, and denying that anything is worthy of reverence.”
The “joy of life is living,” and to live life to
its fullest is “to put out all one’s powers as far
as they will go; that the measure of power is obstacles overcome;
to ride boldly at what is in front of you, be it fence or enemy;
to pray not for comfort, but for combat.” Remarking about
the soldiers of his generation, Holmes said, “We have
shared the incommunicable experience of war; we have felt, we
still feel, the passion of life to its top.”
By
evading the experience of combat, the civilian absentees had
missed a “great good fortune.” Neither money nor
fame -- the familiar ends of pursuit in civil society -- could
compare with a young man’s experience of combat, of having
his young, callow heart “touched with fire.” To
be touched with fire meant for Holmes that the young men who
fought had their valor, and therefore their manhood, tested
in the most excruciating terms. From this tribulation, Holmes
and his fellow soldiers learned what it meant to embrace a passion
to the fullest, to give everything that a man could muster for
a moral cause and to receive in turn the greatest fulfillment
of manliness.
Holmes
acknowledged his ignorance about life’s ultimate ends
(“I do not know the meaning of the universe”). But,
there is something that he finds to be “true” and
“adorable” -- the soldier’s faith. What makes
this faith so noble for Holmes is that it is tested under inconceivable
stress.
There
is an ethereal and cold quality in Holmes’s descriptions
of war; he sketches a world of disembodied, faceless men immersed
in abstract conflicts. In the excerpts that I quoted, Holmes
does not speak of the camaraderie of soldiers. The journalist
Sebastian Junger does at length, however. Junger spent fifteen
months in 2007 and 2008 embedded with the 173d Airborne in Afghanistan.
A powerful reason why men are attracted to combat, Junger argues,
was because they want to protect each other. Combat represents
not merely horror but, for some of the soldiers, an opportunity
to test their love for each other. Junger remarks that “perfectly
sane, good men have been drawn back to combat over and over
again, and anyone interested in the idea of world peace would
do well to know what they’re looking for.” It was
not killing per se but “the other side of the equation:
protecting.” Based on his observations in Afghanistan,
Junger comments: “The defense of the tribe is an insanely
compelling idea, and once you’ve been exposed to it, there’s
almost nothing else you’d rather do. The only reason anyone
was alive [at the base camp] was because every man up there
was willing to die to defend it.”
Bear
in mind: The collective defense Junger alludes to is not reducible
to rational calculation. It was a test of the men’s valour,
to what extent they would sacrifice themselves for the next
man in the battalion. And collective defense, at some point,
became its own end: For the soldiers in the 173d Airborne, “collective
defense can be so compelling -- so addictive, in fact -- that
eventually it becomes the rationale for why the group exists
in the first place.”
The
paradoxical and symbiotic relationship between loathing and
desire in manly courage is evident in Junger’s observation:
“It was everyone’s worst nightmare but also the
thing they hoped for most, some ultimate demonstration of the
bond and fighting ability of the men.” By being that which
“they hoped for most” and an “ultimate demonstration”
of both their collective “bond” and their individual
“fighting ability,” the defense of the battalion
spoke to the same impressions that found their way into Holmes’s
speeches.
THE THIRD PARADOX: WHEN COURAGE HAS NO TIME -- OR DESIRE --
TO REGARD ITSELF AS COURAGE
Logic
would seem to require courage to be contemplative. For courage,
however defined, requires its possessor to know that what he
does is dangerous and to know that danger in the correct proportion.
Consider a familiar authority in the Webster’s Dictionary,
which defines courage as the “mental or moral strength
enabling one to venture, persevere, and withstand danger.”
Embedded in the definition is the assumption that courage, before
it can “venture, persevere, and withstand” some
danger, must first recognize the existence of that danger. Under
this formulation, if you casually walk over a land mine thinking
that it is some random bump in the road, you are not acting
bravely; you are acting ignorantly and, if there was good cause
for you to have known about the land mine, foolishly. William
Tecumseh Sherman, the fierce Northern general in the Civil War,
insists that a knowledge of danger is a prerequisite for courage:
“I would define true courage to be a perfect sensibility
of the measure of danger, and a mental willingness to incur
it, rather than insensibility to danger of which I have heard
far more than seen.”
The
thesis advanced by General Sherman and Webster’s Dictionary
-- that to be courageous you have to know that what you do is
dangerous and know it to the correct degree -- is examined famously,
if rather briefly, by Plato. Written in 380 B.C., Plato’s
Laches involves a debate between Nicias and Laches
about the meaning of courage. Socrates is asked by the two men
to mediate their dispute, and during the arguments, Nicias remarks
that “there is a difference, to my way of thinking, between
fearlessness and courage.” Before someone is dubbed courageous,
he must have thought meaningfully about the danger that he sought
to overcome or endure.
There
is one problem that immediately attends the account of courage
on offer by Nicias, which is essentially the same as that wrought
by Webster’s Dictionary and General Sherman.
Nicias implies that courage is contingent on recognizing the
danger, and hence, overcoming a fear of that danger, yet those
circumstances in which soldiers are most required to prompt
their courage do not afford opportunity for such deliberation.
Therefore, we do not know what, if not courage, is impelling
such outward daring.
Read
again General Sherman’s definition of courage: “I
would define true courage to be a perfect sensibility of the
measure of danger, and a mental willingness to incur it, rather
than insensibility to danger of which I have heard far more
than seen.” Perfect sensibility of both the measure of
danger and the willingness to incur it? How would anyone be
able to make even ballpark guesses of either element in a given
situation where he finds himself having to react within seconds?
Soldiers
also throw themselves into peril without being conscious that
what they do is courageous. Sebastian Junger observed of the
173rd Airborne that “the combat medic’s first job
is to get to the wounded as fast as possible, which often means
running through gunfire. Medics are renowned for their bravery,”
Junger writes, “but the ones I knew described it more
as a terror of failing to save the lives of their friends.”
Junger
reports that “most firefights go by so fast that acts
of bravery or cowardice are more or less spontaneous.”
He elaborates: “Soldiers might live the rest of their
lives regretting a decision that they don’t even remember
making; they might receive a medal for doing something that
was over before they even knew they were doing it.”
Combat’s
success, therefore, hinges in part on not thinking about dangers
and, ironically, not thinking about corollary issues of courage.
As Philip Caputo remarks of his experiences in Vietnam, when
you are away from combat “there was too much time to think,”
but in combat “there would be very little time to think.”
For Caputo, “that is the secret to emotional survival
in war, not thinking.” Thus reads the paradox, then: the
more you are required to be brave, the less you are actually
able to assess whether you are brave when circumstances most
demand it.
JUST
THE WAY YOU ARE . . .
Two
years ago, the pop star Bruno Mars released a song, ubiquitously
broadcast in every Burger King, supermarket, and dentist-office-reception
area in the United States, and which shares the same title as
Billy Joel’s “Just the Way You Are.” Billy
sweetly, and in his own style, discreetly, crooned in the 1970s
that, although he did not know about the rest of the world,
he would “love you just the way you are,” but Bruno
went one better (or worse, depending on your view). Bruno sang
-- no, celebrated -- that you were “aaah—mayyy—zingg.
. . just . . . the . . . way . . . you . . . are . . .”
and that “when you smile, the whole world stops and stares
for a while.” You, blessed reader, are no longer just
lovable in the eyes of one, as you were in the ‘70s; in
the 2010s, you are now amazing in the eyes of all. Amazing,
indeed. Simply for being you. Perhaps it is a sign of our times,
in the early twenty-first century, with its democratic narcissism,
that such an unblushingly idiotic paean to self-esteem is received
without irony as a species of pedestrian praise.
But
no matter how frequently Bruno Mars is, like some nightmarish
Orwellian propaganda, played everywhere we go, indoctrinating
us with the message that all of us are “amazing”
for no other reason than we have blood coursing through our
carotid arteries, one thing remains the same: No man can consider
himself a true man, or be seen as one, without the perceived
possession of courage, that most manly of virtues. No man, according
to society, is amazing, or even plain acceptable, unless he
proves his mettle. That does not mean that courage alone will
suffice to make you a man but, for good or ill, without it,
no one will think of you as one.
Easier
said than done, though. For courage, as I have suggested, is
weirdly paradoxical. Courage is sometimes impelled by the vilest
feminine vice, cowardice. Courage, conventionally understood
as the overcoming of a loathsome fear, is sometimes head drunk
in love with that ostensive object of fear. Courage needs time
to calibrate the danger and what is necessary to overcome the
fear attending that danger, but courage has no time for such
measure when courage is most necessary.
If
courage is so paradoxical, so barbed, how do we make sense of
it as the supremely male virtue? How do we make sense, in short,
of what it means to be a man?