Arts & Opinion.com
  Arts Culture Analysis  
Vol. 3, No. 1, 2004
 

     
  Current Issue  
  Back Issues  
  About  
 
 
  Submissions  
  Subscribe  
  Comments  
  Letters  
  Contact  
  Jobs  
  Ads  
  Links  
 
 
  Editor
Robert J. Lewis
 
  Contributing Editors
Bernard Dube
Phil Nixon
Mark Goldfarb
Robert Rotondo
 
  Music Editor
Emanuel Pordes
 
  Arts Editor
Marissa Consiglieri de Chackal
 
  Graphics
Mady Bourdage
 
  Webmaster
Emanuel Pordes
 
 
 
  Past Contributors
 
  Noam Chomsky
Robert Fisk
Pico Iyer
Edward Said
Mark Kingwell
Arundhati Roy
Naomi Klein
Jean Baudrillard
John Lavery
David Solway
Tariq Ali
Michael Albert
Rochelle Gurstein
 
     
THE LAW OF WAR AND SOVEREIGN EXCEPTION

by Scott MICHAELSEN and Scott Cutler SHERSHOW


Scott Michaelsen and David Johnson are co-editors of The New Centennial Reivew. The Guantánamo "Black Hole": The Law of War and the Sovereign Exception was originally published in MERIP (The Midde East Report).

______________________________________

 

THE LIEBER CODE

The humanitarian laws of war were first codified by legal philosopher Francis Lieber at a time long before the Geneva Conventions. The "Lieber Code," which directly influenced both the Hague deliberations at the turn of the century, and the Geneva Conventions in the mid-twentieth century, was put into effect on April 24, 1863 by Abraham Lincoln's secretary of war, Edwin Stanton. As Paragraph 155 of the Code clearly indicates, there are only two classes of persons in warfare: "All enemies in a regular war are divided into two general classes -- that is to say, into combatants and non-combatants, or unarmed citizens of the hostile government." Intriguingly, before the Code's existence in 1862, the general-in-chief of the US Army, Major General Henry Halleck, had already corresponded with Lieber regarding the exceptional problem of "guerrilla war." Lieber's 22-page reply was published before the Code itself became public and went into effect. In other words, in the history of the codification of the laws of war, the exception to the normative rules came first, providing the strange ground for the norm itself.

Lieber's letter on the guerrilla operates via a kind of double logic of the exception. Lieber is primarily concerned to distinguish between legal combatants entitled "to the full benefits of the laws of war" and "guerrillas" who are not. But as Lieber defines the term, the guerrilla is constituted by a variety of "kindred subjects," among them figures variously named the "freebooter," the "brigand," the "partisan" and so on. "Partisans," for example, are soldiers "detached from the main army" who resemble, and yet must be distinguished from, a "free corps" made up of "volunteers, generally raised by individuals authorized to do so by the government." Even though the members of this last sub-category are often "high-minded patriots," they are still to be rejected as unlawful combatants and treated "on the principle of retaliation." (This "retaliation," as Lieber makes clear in his formal code, refers to indiscriminate violence that can even include the killing of prisoners of war. "The law of war can no more wholly dispense with retaliation than can the law of nations," he insists.) By the same token, the category of lawful combatant cannot simply be limited to the regular uniformed soldiers of an organized army. Lieber also suggests, for example, that "the rising of the people to repel invasion entitles them to the full benefits of the law of war" and that a conquering power is "obliged to treat the captured citizens in arms as prisoners of war."

At one and the same time, Lieber charts a variety of fine distinctions between otherwise similar practices, as he also draws a fundamental line beyond which all distinctions dissolve, and where all combatants, regardless of their specific motivations, are to be treated as "common robbers" and subject, if necessary, to indiscriminate violence. The law and practice of war thus remains inextricably linked to the limitless barbarism that it always seeks to transcend.

This double logic is deeply interwoven into the history of sovereignty and even the development of American constitutional democracy. Consider Lieber's description of one sub-category of illegal combatant:

"Freebooter is a term which was in common use in the English language at no very remote period; it is of rare use now, because the freebooter makes his appearance but rarely in modern times, thanks to the more regular and efficient governments and to the more advanced state of the law of war. From the freebooter at sea arose the privateer, for the privateer is a commissioned freebooter, or the freebooter taken into the service of the government by the letter of marque . . . Wherever the freebooter is taken, at sea or on land, death is inflicted upon him now as in former times, for freebooters are nothing less than armed robbers of the most dangerous and criminal type."

The privateer, a kind of state-sanctioned pirate, highlights the elusive but implacable distinction between legal and illegal combatant. The bonafide pirate -- the genuinely "private" privateer -- has typically been described with the same rhetoric of exceptionality today applied to the terrorist, as someone who, in the words of Sir William Blackstone, "is an offence against the universal law of society," and who "has reduced himself afresh to the savage state of nature." It is striking to note how Article I, section 8 of the Constitution, in two sequential clauses of unmistakable symmetry, gives to Congress the power "to define and punish piracies and felonies committed on the high seas, and offences against the law of nations," and also, "to declare war, grant letters of marque and reprisal, and make rules concerning captures on land and water." The archaic term "letter of marque," as Lieber's text also indicates, refers to the practice of authorizing a naval privateer to attack the enemies of a state and thus (according to the Oxford English Dictionary) "to commit acts which would otherwise have constituted piracy." In effect, state sovereignty literally consists at once of the power to punish and to commit piracy. Terrorism also presents the sovereign state with an image of its own essential violence, which in turn calls forth the violent exceptionality of the state's response.

Such a conclusion is no mere theoretical sophistry or legal technicality, as seen in the public discourse surrounding the "war on terrorism." Speaking on NPR, the famous law professor Alan Dershowitz defended the arrest of two female relatives of Izzat Ibrahim al-Duri, the former top adviser to Saddam Hussein accused of involvement in recent attacks on US forces in Iraq. "It's never permissible under international law or under American domestic law to hold an innocent person in order to put pressure on a relative or a guilty person," Dershowitz began by conceding, "but the United States is experimenting with what might generously be called creative approaches to the problem of terrorist prevention." Such "creative" approaches are justified, he goes on to suggest, "because international law wasn't written for terrorism." Dershowitz is quite wrong on this point as a matter of historical fact, as the above analysis of the Lieber Code shows. Yet his frank embrace of this particular transgression of international law is wholly in keeping with the underlying assumptions of that system. Perhaps even more strikingly, New York Times columnist David Brooks excused "the brutal measures our own troops will have to adopt" in fighting the war in Iraq. Because the US military is fighting people who "survive only by cruelty," he claimed, it will have to respond with what he frankly calls "atrocities."

 

SOVEREIGNTY AGAINST ITSELF

The act of sovereignty that captures the Guantánamo detainees only to push them beyond the reach and protection of the sovereign state is the very manifestation of the existing state system and its corollary values. Critics are confronted with a Hobson's choice between attempting to limit or suspend the exercise of sovereignty through increasing legal regulation or endorsing the exercise of sovereignty as a necessary corrective to injustice (as in the king's or executive's pardon). On this point, progressive legal theorists have been split. But the ultimate answer cannot lie solely in the enforcement of existing international law and the production of yet more international documents within the same framework, nor in the tenuous hope for occasional exceptions to that sovereign exceptionality that is always the essential form of sovereign power. International law alone will never avail, and not merely because its own logic always holds in reserve a right to the same indiscriminate violence that it condemns in the guerrilla, the pirate or the terrorist. Sovereignty is the principle and activity that founds the state, and therefore constitutes its innermost and outermost possibility. The sovereign black hole, loophole or zone of legal limbo is foundational for the existing juridico-political order. Even more broadly, within that order, the absolute end of sovereignty is unthinkable. Without sovereignty, no decisions; and without decisions, no justice.

Since sovereignty itself is inevitable, yet particular instances of sovereign power must still be confronted and challenged, critics of the current situation must assume a double responsibility. On the one hand, the present resources of national and international law must indeed be pursued to their limits, to discover and interpret precedents for the urgent decisions of the day, and, more importantly, to set new precedents for decisions still to come. But on the other hand, since law itself cannot in principle ever be adequate to the full enormity of Guantánamo, sovereignty itself must be torqued in a strange reversal, and made to work against itself. In other words, the sovereignty of strong states with the power to decide global matters -- the sovereignty that is, after all, finally a collective force, a power "of the people, by the people and for the people" -- must be expended without reserve in the name, not of law, but of justice, to the point where the territory and its boundary trembles. Such an undertaking will not yield a mechanism or method that might be codified, because it will involve sovereign (and hence unprecedented) acts and decisions; and because its goal is a justice understood as an infinite task of thinking our relation to the Other. But as Jacques Derrida suggests, "the fact that law is deconstructible is not bad news"; rather, one can "find in this the political chance to all historical progress." All this is perhaps difficult to imagine in a world so dominated by reasons of state and the fanaticism of borders and identities. But the urgency of the task can hardly be overstated. At any rate, one thing is clear: at Guantánamo Bay, as Walt Kelly once observed, "we have met the enemy and he is us."


 

E-Tango Creative Web Design
Core-Net Computer Services
ColbaNet
Caribbean Report
Available Ad Space
Donations
Valid HTML 4.01!
Privacy Statement Contact Info
Copyright 2002 Robert J. Lewis