colin mcginn's
THE MEANING OF DISGUST
reviewed by
SCOTT McLEMEE
______________________________
Scott
McLemee's reviews, essays and interviews have appeared in The
New York Times, The Washington Post, The Boston
Globe, The Nation, Newsday, The Common
Review and numerous other publications including insidehighered.com,
where this article first appeared. For more of Scott, check
out his blog.
The
chemical formula for sugar is not sweet -- and a philosopher’s
ideas about disgust are, by the same principle, not themselves
disgusting. On the other hand, it is hard to analyze the experience
of disgust without evoking it, or at least coming up with thought
experiments that are pretty distasteful. This column is about
Colin McGinn’s new book, The Meaning of Disgust (Oxford
University Press). I mention this in case anyone is eating.
You might want to come back when you're done. There will be
effluvia.
McGinn,
a professor of philosophy at the University of Miami, is a prolific
and wide-ranging author, but rather a latecomer to the topic.
Quite a bit of work has been done lately in the humanities regarding
emotion or affect, variously informed by cognitive research,
evolutionary theory and psychoanalysis. I have no statistics
to back this up -- just a rough sense from keeping an eye out
over the years -- but it seems as if negative affects receive
most of the attention, with shame in particular getting the
lion’s share.
The
literature on disgust is not quite as abundant, but there’s
still plenty of it. The most incisive and stimulating volume
on the subject, to my knowledge anyway, is William Ian Miller’s
The Anatomy of Disgust (Harvard University Press,
1997), while Martha Nussbaum provides an extensive and judicious
assessment of the interdisciplinary literature in Hiding
From Humanity: Shame, Disgust, and the Law (Princeton University
Press, 2004). Nussbaum’s thinking on the matter -- which
she revisited in From Disgust to Humanity: Sexual Orientation
and Constitutional Law, published last year by Oxford University
Press -- is in part a reply to the work of Leon Kass, a professor
of social thought at the University of Chicago and chairman
of the President’s Commission on Bioethics during the
administration of George W. Bush.
Kass
understands disgust to be the product of moral wisdom expressing
itself at a visceral level, “beyond reason’s power
fully to articulate it.” In the shudder of disgust, human
nature “revolts against the excesses of human willfulness,
warning us not to transgress what is unspeakably profound.”
It is possible to make rational arguments against cannibalism,
incest, bestiality, or the mutilating of corpses; but such reasoning
lacks the raw suasive power of nausea.
So
Kass maintains while making a case against human cloning. “Revulsion
is not an argument,” he admits, “and some of yesterday’s
repugnances are today calmly accepted -- though, one must add,
not always for the better.” Calmly accepting cloning,
then, would be a crime against our deeper wisdom. At this point
it would seem obligatory to explain how we can distinguish “deep
moral wisdom”-type disgust from the old “Klansman
shooting interracial couple” sort. All the more so given
that Kass played an entirely honorable role in the Civil Rights
movement. But he offers no clarification. Disgust is a source
of interesting and difficult problems, but it doesn’t
offer much of a solution to anything.
Disgust
is paradoxical -- “both an aversive and an attractive
emotion,” writes McGinn. Either way, it exerts a powerful
claim on one’s attention. “Disgust is not boring,”
he writes. “It has a kind of negative glamour.”
But
how is it that we are susceptible to that dark glamour? Animals
seem not to manifest disgust, nor do humans until sometime around
age 3. Dogs and very small children are notoriously fascinated
with excrement (their own and otherwise). What counts as disgusting
can vary from one society to the next. Whether you find escargot,
haggis, or pork rinds to be delicious or nauseating is a matter
of cultural conditioning. In spite of such local variations,
though, the range of kinds of things eliciting disgust seems
limited. From era to era and culture to culture, the feeling
of disgust tends to focus on some aspect of ingestion, excretion,
sexuality, or death -- or some shudder-inducing combination
thereof.
Conversely,
not just anything can be experienced as disgusting. (People
use the word a bit loosely at times, often while angry or frustrated;
but real disgust involves revulsion and a sense of possible
contamination). It’s hard to imagine anyone, however squeamish,
feeling disgust for a laptop computer or a redwood tree.
We
are dealing, then, with an emotion that is somewhat flexible
but by no means arbitrary, with a particular emphasis on the
flesh -- its weaknesses, its smells, its mortality, and (most
of all) various behaviours and byproducts just south of the
navel. We have lofty ideas, we fart and we die. Not, one hopes,
all at the same time, though the vulnerability is disobliging
in any event.
McGinn
runs through various theories about the dynamics and evolutionary
benefits of disgust, and his phenomenological treatment of the
feeling shares a lot with the thinking of other authors. Whatever
the origins and cross-cultural variations, though, his real
interest is in what it means that we are uniquely disgust-prone
creatures. The salient thing is that disgust is the mind’s
unhappy response to evidence that it is trapped in an animal
that will one day rot. It is also an attempt to control that
animal by putting a damper on human desire, which is polymorphous
and insatiable: “Disgust is the human psyche policing
itself, putting up self-imposed barriers.”
The
problem being, of course, that the barriers don’t hold.
A mind that polices itself can also plea-bargain with itself.
The human condition seems defined by the relationship between
desire and disgust, which seems unstable and treacherous. They
can also blend together in all sorts of really strange ways.
(It seems at times as if the Internet exists to document this
fact).
McGinn’s
most influential work has been on the mind-body problem. “We
know,” he wrote in a major paper, “that brains are
the de facto causal basis of consciousness, but we have, it
seems, no understanding whatever of how this can be so . . .
Neural transmissions just seem like the wrong kind of materials
with which to bring consciousness into the world, but it appears
that in some way they perform this mysterious feat.”
His
argument is that we can’t bridge the gap between brain
pulp and the mind’s eye, and never will. No need for dualism.
We can assume that the mind is indeed a product of the brain’s
operations. And we can learn more and more about those operations
themselves. But the existence of the mind will remain mind-boggling,
even so. Human thought is a puzzle for itself that, because
of some limitation in its powers, it cannot solve.
One
response to this is awe. Another, which comes more frequently,
is disgust. McGinn’s understanding of disgust as a response
to excess (a brake on unchecked desire) is a long way from treating
it as a wellspring of reliable moral guidance. It is one more
manifestation of the mind-body problem: the unpleasant reminder
that a creature able to imagine its own immortality is "born
between urine and feces.”